Gene Editing: How much justice delayed or denied?

Nicholas G. Evans offers a nuanced examination of John Harris’ claims against the “unacceptable risks to future generations” associated with gene editing in human reproduction.

__________________________________________

The International Summit on Human Gene Editing: A Global Discussion is a three-day event convened by the Chinese Academy of Sciences, The Royal Society, the United States (US) National Academy of Sciences, and US National Academy of Medicine. The Summit has a live webcast, a vibrant Twitter hashtag, and is being reported by major news organizations and blogs alike.

I want to pick up on one very small piece of this immense puzzle, highlighted by philosopher John Harris in the penultimate session of day one of the Summit (you can find his talk here). Harris, at the University of Manchester, highlighted three allegedly “obviously fallacious and dogmatic” arguments against the editing of the human genome:

  • Arguments from the sacredness of the human genome;
  • Arguments from the “unacceptable risks to future generations” as a result of human gene editing;
  • The inability to get consent from children produced as a result of human gene editing.

I want to pick up the second of these, and concentrate solely on the question of editing the human genome in embryos, which is Harris’ main talking point. Harris notes that the risks of gene editing of the germ line only have to be comparable to the “gold standard” of human reproduction. As such, Harris wants us to conclude, we should press forward with gene editing insofar as it is no more risky than our alternatives, including the risks posed by already accepted reproductive technologies (IVF, preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), etc.).

GetFileAttachment

The problem is that Harris’ argument is incomplete, because the argument he purports to debunk is itself incomplete. While some surely think that the risks of human gene editing are unacceptable independent of any potential benefits (a strong “precautionary principle,” which Harris—unfairly, I think—dismisses outright), most arguments turn on the risks we can expect from a technology, weighed against its benefits.

Framed this way, Harris’ argument stumbles. The common answer to “what are the benefits of gene editing?” is “we’ll cure genetic diseases and save lives!” When this claim is interrogated, however, it isn’t clear how many lives we’re talking about. This ought to matter to Harris, whose argument, at least at the Summit, relied on the prospect of many people being saved, and where gene editing was necessary to the survival of those people. (I set aside Harris’ transhumanist claims for the sake of brevity.)

Yet the final session on day one of the Summit was an exercise in uncertainty: hundreds, or even thousands, of separate genes inform most common diseases with genetic components. Changing all of these is unlikely to be practical or safe, and would not so much “cure” a person, but rather lower their risk of getting that disease. For genetic diseases like Huntington’s disease that are autosomal dominant, where the presence of a single particular gene in a non sex-linked chromosome will cause the disease, there’s little reason why our first line intervention wouldn’t be Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis, where we select an embryo that doesn’t have the gene for that disease. For couples where one partner has two dominant genes for a disease—and thus 100% chance of passing on that gene, and the disease, to their progeny—gene editing would be a net benefit. The problem is that this scenario is incredibly rare: Eric Lander, speaking in the final session of day one of the Summit, noted that only about a dozen such cases of Huntington’s have been recorded.

Gene editing is important and beneficial; there are people out there whose lives, and whose children’s lives, will be made better with this technology. But Harris’ claims about the benefits of gene editing have to be moderated. Again, this should matter to Harris: if he wants to say, regarding a moratorium on gene editing humans, that “justice delayed is justice denied,” he has to point to the injustice. For a wide range of diseases, this injustice could be rectified with other approaches, such as increasing access to genetic screening of parents (and genetic counselors), and Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis—gene editing doesn’t have to play a part. Some will go without, but this number is surely no larger than in diseases that are neglected by funding agencies—if anything, caution about the benefits and harms of technology seems a good reason to delay, rather than mere neglect of a disease.

And here, Harris has to answer the thornier question of why we ought to invest in this technology for comparably limited clinical benefit, compared to, say, any one of a range of neglected tropical diseases whose mortality far outstrips genetic diseases. If the number of lives saved is Harris’ primary metric, his enthusiasm for gene editing doesn’t appear to be proportionate to the expected benefits of the technology. A mere appeal to lives saved doesn’t get him the traction he wants.

__________________________________________

Nicholas G. Evans is a Postdoctoral Fellow in Advanced Biomedical Ethics in the Department of Medical Ethics and Health Policy at the University of Pennsylvania @neva9257

2 comments

  1. This article is garbage.

    You literally admit that germline gene editing is the only way to have a related disease-free child in some cases (e.g. homozygous for huntingtons). There are many other cases, such as where a couple are both homozygous for a recessive disease, which is quite common in disease communities where the disease brings people together. The same applies where couples don’t produce enough embryos for PGD, as some couples produce as low as one embryo, and this would be an even bigger problem when multiple traits are being selected.

    So given that some people would seriously benefit from this technology, it seems the best argument you have for prohibiting it is when you question “why we ought to invest in this technology for comparably limited clinical benefit, compared to, say, any one of a range of neglected tropical diseases whose mortality far outstrips genetic diseases”.

    If you don’t want to invest in it because it will save fewer lives than investing in something else, then that simply means the government should not invest in it. You would have no problem with legalising it and letting the research/trials be privately paid for.

    Also, the unacceptable risks to future generations rhetoric is nonsense. Do you write an article here every time a pregnant woman drinks alcohol heavily? (legal in most of the West and federally in the US). What about every time a man smokes, as smoking literally mutates sperm cell genomes and is passed on indefinitely. The only difference with gene editing is that it is deliberate, which makes it better since it is more precise than the random mutations that are already legal. If the predicted benefits are estimated to be greater than the risks, then it should be legalised like every single other medicine (for children or not) which has both risks or benefits.

  2. Deborah Rosen · · Reply

    Thank you so very much for this article, I also would rather be careful and reduce suffering to the already born.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: